Related Posts with Thumbnails
Mostrando entradas con la etiqueta Queen Mary University of London. Mostrar todas las entradas
Mostrando entradas con la etiqueta Queen Mary University of London. Mostrar todas las entradas

domingo, 21 de marzo de 2010

64

Mi intención es estudiar Economía y Política (LL12), pero leyendo tu blog no sé si me he metido en un berenjenal de mucho cuidado.
Andrés Horcajo



¡Hoy, oficialmente primer día de primavera el sol ha decidido visitar Londres! Se estaba genial bebiendo Iced Tea al lado del canal, o dando un paseo en bicicleta por el parque... pero hay examen, y a la biblioteca fui de cabeza. Examen el lunes, avisado el viernes. Examen de un libro completo de 300 páginas. En fin, después del desastre del otro examen de macroeconomía, habrá que enseñarle a este señor lo bien que sabemos hacer los exámenes los españoles. Hay otro examen el martes de micro, que todavía no me he empezado a preparar (tocará empezar una vez acabado el examen de macro, mañana a las 4 de la tarde, y seguramente habrá que aguantar un all-nighter, hola Redbull sin azúcar) y después, lo que queda de semana es relajado y feliz hasta que coja el vuelo a Madrid el viernes. ¡Ya puedo oler el incienso y el azahar! Aunque como aquí no se celebra la Semana Santa (las vacaciones son de pascua, tres semanas) me voy a saltar la última semana de curso, pero no pasa nada, son todo sesiones de repaso que no me an a beneficiar mucho de todas maneras. Mañana me toca recoger el calendario de exámenes, ¡esperemos que pueda estar libre antes de Junio! Como no me echan de la casa hasta Julio, pues aprovecharé para sacar el carné de conducir.

Aparte de exámenes, el viernes me devolvieron una de las redacciones, aquella sobre la justicia. he sacado un... ¡¡¡¡64!!! Estoy más que contento, he sido la mejor nota de mi clase (aunque no del curso) pero es una mejoría sustancial... el camino hacía el siete es empinado pero llegaremos, Johny, llegaremos. La redacción la dejo abajo por si a alguien le interesa ver (aunque lo dudo) la aplicación que da la política a la justicia. A lo mejor algún futuro abogado se interesa por las teorías de Rawls... que de hecho, son muy interesantes.

Dentro de poco inauguraré una nueva sección del blog, o a lo mejor un blog nuevo, todavía no lo he decidido, bastante interesante... ¡secreto, secreto! En realidad no lo es tanto... el título será "Secret London Review" (SLR), creo que eso lo dice todo. ¡Ya estoy escribiendo la primera entrada! En cuanto acabe los exámenes...

Así que por lo demás nada, que espero que esteis todos bien y disfrutando del sol en España.

Salud!

Version:1.0 StartHTML:0000000234 EndHTML:0000048453 StartFragment:0000004098 EndFragment:0000048417 SourceURL:file://localhost/Users/Bosco/Documents/Politics/Introduction%20to%20politics/Do%20Jon%20Rawls'%20two%20principles.doc

Do John Rawls’ two principles of justice succeed in uniting the principle of liberty with the ideal of equality?

ABSTRACT

John Rawls proposes two principles of justice in his book “A theory of Justice”: justice should be based in access to the most extensive scheme of basic liberties and inequalities should be to everyone’s advantage. Through this principles he creates a web in which justice is completely supported by equality and liberty, in a situation in which one cannot exist without the other two. The implication of equality in justice is proved with the assertion that justice can only be applied to equal beings. The implication of liberty, through a society of equal beings in which therefore liberty is the obedience to general will. Once proved both implications examples are provided: through equality of opportunity and obedience to the general will Rawls’ success is proved. After a brief analysis of the criticisms, the conclusion is that, even if a presence of the natural right in his work is desirable he succeeds in uniting the three concepts.

Uniting the ideal of equality with the principle of liberty through two principles of justice is one of the many ideas that John Rawls attempted in his book “A theory of justice”, first published in 1971. However, the question itself implies many other questions that can arise before the study begins. What do we mean by ideal of equality and principle of liberty? Does justice comprise liberty and equality? Does the ideal of equality imply the non-existence of inequalities? Does liberty limit equality? Or vice versa? Does justice limit them both? But most important of all, how does justice unite liberty and equality? And do Rawls’ principles achieve this? The aim of this essay is to provide rational answers to these questions and analyse the union of liberty and equality that can emerge from Rawls’ two principles.

Justice has had different meanings through the history of political thought. From Aristotle’s definition “refraining from pleonexia[1] (In the sense that a situation is just as long as an individual does not gain advantage for himself by taking hold of another individual’s properties) through the utilitarianism of Bentham, one of the latest theories of justice is that of John Rawls. In the book mentioned above, “A theory of Justice”, Rawls states that the principles of justice should be determined by “the choice which rational men would make in the hypothetical situation of equal liberty”[2], that is, the rules that men (and women) would agree to base their society on, if they were absolutely identical, or, as Rawls defines it, under “a veil of ignorance” that would prevent them to know their social position in society, their own abilities and capacities, sex or race.

In the Rawlsian jargon, the previous situation is known as the “original position”. From this original position is where the rational men and women stated above will agree in the principles of justice. Rawls calls his theory “justice as fairness”, since “it conveys the idea that the principles of justice are agreed to in an initial situation that is fair” (the original position).[3] The two principles are as follows:[4]

1. Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others.

2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are: A) Reasonably expected to be to everyone’s advantage, and B) attached to positions and offices open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.

If these two principles are to set the basis of justice, it can be agreed that injustice occurs whenever they are not observed. Society or individuals, then, are unjust when they restrict other’s liberties or opportunities, or when they allow the existence of inequalities that are not to the advantage of every person. To prevent injustice, Rawls states that justice should be taken as “a complex of three ideas: liberty, equality and reward for services contributing to the common good.”[5]

Barbara Goodwin defines equality as “the first assumption of morality”[6], that is, that morality needs to be based in equality, since individuals do not need or tend to act morally with others considered inferior. Only those considered as equal or superior will deserve a moral treatment. When relating it to justice, different types of equality come to mind: equality before the law, political equality (all men are equal to women, black are equal to white, etc with respect to access to office, suffrage…), and the most important of all, equality of opportunity. The latter is even implied directly in principle II-b, and it will be developed later on.

It is clear that equality is a fundamental part of justice, since without humans being equal there could be no sense of just society in the sense that Rousseau described (and that Rawls shares): “private concerns become considerably fewer, because each individual shares so largely in the common happiness that he has no occasion to seek for it in private resources.”[7] In this just society, individuals are so equal that the public affaires are what becomes important. From here it can be concluded that the ideal of equality comprises a society in which all individuals are equal politically and before the law, and have all equal access to opportunities. Living in this ideal of equality provides the background for a competitive justice to operate.

The second idea that conforms justice is liberty (or freedom). Since the seventeenth century, political thought and philosophy agree that only free men can have access to justice. This is supported by the idea of equality, since non-free persons are, in a sense, inferior to those who are, and therefore they should not have access to a justice designed to be used by equal individuals. These theories have evolved and now state that, all men are equal then all have the right to be free; in fact, as a matter of justice, it is an injustice to cut anyone’s liberty. However, there are different ways to understand liberty. In its extreme sense (“I do what I want, how and when I want to”) liberty itself can be unjust, because it can strike other’s liberties or rights (for example, if an individual chooses not to pay taxes he is abusing of the other taxpayers, etc). This is the kind of liberty that Rawls is referring to when he speaks about “the most extensive scheme of basic liberties”: the most extensive scheme, which can be restricted by law, society or moral. However, there are other ways to understand liberty, the most important of them the one that Rousseau proposes: liberty as obedience to the general will. This conception of liberty is perfectly compatible to the conception of equality seen above, in which individuals are absolutely equal.

However there is an important difference (that Rawls remarks) between the sense of equality as a social ideal, that is, a society in which all have the same rights, privileges and duties independent of their age, position, race, etcetera, and the sense of equality as a concept of justice. It has been said above that equality is a requirement for justice, but it is clear that an equal treatment is not sufficient for justice to exist. Liberty has a priority role in the Theory of Justice: it is unjust not to have access to the basic liberties. In fact, Rawls summarizes the importance of both when he claims that “justice requires only an equal liberty.”[8] Liberty is then restricted by equality; only what economists call “Pareto efficiency” is allowed: liberty can be exercised in order to make an individual better off, if and only if that exercise does not make any other individual worse off. The equality of liberty, therefore, limits positive liberty but enhances in exchange the negative, since (all individuals having equal liberties) interference between them is not necessary. From here it can be concluded that the existence of inequality implies injustice, and vice versa. As said before, equality and liberty in the sense of justice hold hands, so it can be also concluded that an injustice entails as well a lack of liberty.

Principle II-b defines the most important role of equality in the Rawlsian conception of justice: justice as fair equality of opportunity. From the individuals in a society, “those with similar abilities and skills should have similar life chances.”[9] Equality of opportunity is one of the ways through which the union of justice with liberty and equality can be proved. Fair equality of opportunity implies liberty of choice: for example, in a society in which “positions and offices are open to all”[10], as the second principle states, the individuals have the liberty to choose to which position or office are they going to apply for, if they apply for any. In a broader sense, in the second principle, Rawls is explaining how the inequalities should be distributed. That means that there is the assumption that inequalities are always going to exist, therefore the ideal of equality as the non-existence of inequalities is reformulated by Rawls. Inequalities are always going to exist in a society; as a result, in order for justice to exist, inequalities have to be distributed to everyone’s advantage. The only way in which these inequalities can be allocated in a just way is the one in which they are accepted freely. In the moment an individual is forced to suffer an inequality, an injustice is being perpetrated. That is one example of the ways in which Rawls’ two principles succeed in uniting liberty with equality.

It has been said above that a possible interpretation of liberty is the one Rousseau proposes: liberty as obedience to the general will. That definition is also linked with equality, since only all individuals being equal can they interest themselves more in the public issues than in the private ones. To achieve this concept of liberty, Goodwin clarifies, individuals should “divest themselves of their selfish interests.”[11] Rawls also treats the theme of selfishness in his work, but he calls it envy: “the special assumption I make is that a rational individual does not suffer from envy…”[12]. What can be deduced from the absence of selfishness/envy in both works is that selfishness provokes inequality, i.e. makes us unequal. An easier way to explain this is that if equality is the first asset of morality (as seen above), and selfishness is not moral, selfishness makes us unequal. By eliminating selfishness, the principle of liberty is to obey the general will. The general will can only be obeyed if all individuals are equal, therefore this is another example of the success of the two principles.

Whereas Rawls’s treatment of concepts such as primary goods, status quo and other has been widely criticised in the academic ambit, it is not those in which the essay is based. There have been critics, however, to the enforcement of positive rights (the right to be exposed to an action of other individual) that he applies to various things such as equality of opportunity. Robert Nozick claims that "These 'rights' require a substructure of things and materials and actions (…) and other people may have rights and entitlements over these.”[13] It is precisely this substructure failure what has been lambasted widely. As seen, Nozick and many authors claim that Rawls’ theory is based on erroneous principles, and therefore the principles are flawed and cannot unite any ideals of equality with principles of liberty. Philosopher Allan Bloom denounces the non-existence of the natural right in any point of Rawls’ theory: “disappointingly, A theory of Justice does not even manifest an awareness of this need, let alone respond to it.”[14] Without the basis of natural right and positive rights, they argue, the theory is built over weak pillars. A final criticism is that of Amdur concerning liberty. He states that “Still, Rawls does not want to argue that (…) liberties are absolute”[15], but that “his limits (to liberties) are (…) insignificant”[16], therefore exposing the weakness of Rawls’ argumentation.

Be that as it may, the responses to Rawls’ Theory of Justice focus mainly, as said above, in topics other than the union of the ideal of equality with the principle of liberty through his two principles of justice. In conclusion, the criticism arisen from this work is not strong enough to overshadow Rawls’ reasoning. Even though a presence of Natural right in his work would be desirable, without it, it is perfectly possible to reach the conclusion that he is successful in joining the two concepts through the principle of justice by establishing a web in which liberty, and equality support justice, and any of the elements can exist if one of them is missing, as it has been proved in the examples above.

Bibliography:

Amdur, R. (1977) “Rawls’ theory of justice: domestic and international perspective” published in “World Politics”, Volume 29, Nr. 3

Bloom, A. (1975) “Justice: John Rawls vs. the tradition of political philosophy”, published in The American political Science review, vol. 69, nr 2 Available at http://www.jstor.org/stable/1959094?seq=1&Search=yes&term=bloom&term=allan&term=rawls&term=right&term=natural&list=hide&searchUri=/action/doBasicSearch%3FQuery%3Dallan%2Bbloom%2Brawls%2Bnatural%2Bright%26gw%3Djtx%26prq%3Dallan%2Bbloom%2Brawls%26Search%3DSearch%26hp%3D25%26wc%3Don&item=4&ttl=153&returnArticleService=showArticle&resultsServiceName=doBasicResultsFromArticle. Last accessed 5/3/10, 00.32

Goodwin, B. (2007) “Using political ideas”. Chichester: Wiley

Nozick, R. (1974) “Anarchy, state and utopia”. London: Blackwell

Rawls, J. (1971) “A theory of justice”. Oxford: Oxford university press.

Rawls, J. (1964) “Justice as fairness” in Laslett, P. and Runciman, W. “Philosophy, politics and society”. Oxford: Basil Blackwell

Rousseau, J. (1762) “The social contract”. Book III

Tawney, R. (1931) “Equality”. London: Unwin Brothers

Wolff, R. (1977) “Understanding Rawls”. Guildford: Princeton University Press



[1] Rawls, J. (1971) “A theory of justice”. Oxford: Oxford university press. P. 9

[2] Rawls, J. (1971) Op. Cit. P.11

[3] Rawls, J. (1971) Op. Cit. P.11

[4] Rawls, J. (1971) Op. Cit. P.53 The “fair equality of opportunity” part is added on P. 72

[5] Rawls, J. (1964) “Justice as fairness” in Laslett, P. and Runciman, W. “Philosophy, politics and society”, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, P. 134 (Rawls himself states that these principles can be found on Mill’s “on liberty” and elsewhere).

[6] Goodwin, B. (2007) “Using political ideas”. Chichester: Wiley, P. 417

[7] Rousseau, J. (1762) “The social contract”, Book III, chapter XV

[8] Rawls, J. (1964) “Justice as fairness” in Laslett, P. and Runciman, W. “Philosophy, politics and society”, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, P. 134

[9] Rawls, J. (1971) “A theory of justice”. Oxford: Oxford university press. P. 63

[10] Rawls, J. (1971) Op. Cit. P. 72

[11] Goodwin, B. (2007) “Using political ideas”. Chichester: Wiley, P. 347

[12] Rawls, J. (1971) Op. Cit. P. 125

[13] Nozick, R. (1974) “Anarchy, state and utopia” London: Blackwell, P. 238

[15] Amdur, R. (1977) “Rawls’ theory of justice: domestic and international perspective” published in “World Politics”, Volume 29, Nr. 3 P. 440

[16] Amdur, R. (1977) Op. Cit. P. 441

¡¡Quiero leer más!!

viernes, 5 de marzo de 2010

Mi reino por una tostada


Se trata de los principios que personas racionales y libres interesadas en promover su propio interés aceptarían en una poscición original de igualdad de modo que defina los fundamentos de los términos de su asociación:

Primero: cada persona debe tener un derecho igual al esquema más extenso de libertades básicas iguales compatible con un esquema similar de libertades para otros.

Segundo: Las desigualdades sociales y económicas deben de resolverse de modo tal que:
a) resulten en el mayor beneficio de los miembros menos aventajados de la sociedad
b) los cargos y puestos deben de estar abiertos para todos bajo condiciones de igualdad de oportunidades

John Rawls

Espero que os gustara la celebración de la entrada número 30!! Me parece una buena forma de empezar la decenas, queda instaurada la tradición. La cita al principio, por supuesto, no falta. Hoy pongo los dos principios de la justicia de John Rawls, sobre los que acabo de completar un ensayo (a ver si me dan el 7! A ver si me lo dan!) que ya subiré si me dan una nota aceptable, cosa que espero.

Os recomiendo que os leais estos dos principios de la justicia, pues es la conclusión a la que llegó Rawls tras plantearse la pregunta: "¿Con qué normas estaría yo de acuerdo en que se basase la sociedad, si yo no supiera cuál iba a ser mi lugar en la misma (id est, no se si soy mujer u hombre, presidente o esclavo etc etc). Es interesante planteárse esta pregunta, pensarla y ver con qué soluciones te encuentras. Así que si no has leído lo de arriba con detenimiento, ¿porqué no lo piensas un rato? Venga, piensa, ahora, que nadie mira.

Terminé el ensayo ayer a las 2:30 de la mañana, y hoy hemos tenido ¡¡El segundo simulacro de incendios!! A las 6:30 de la mañana. Después, ya no me he podido volver a dormir. Así que aquí estoy, preparándome la clase de macroeconomía (aunque, ¿Qué utilidad tiene? Si luego de todas maneras, no me entero de nada. Profesor demencial.) de la que por cierto este profesor, al que como veis adoro, puso un Examen Sorpresa (En la universidad?? Venga ya!!!!) que seguramente habré suspendido, yo y el 99.9 por ciento de la clase. Aunque esperaré los resultados. Orgulloso estoy, en cambio, de mi 100% en el pasado examen de mitad de curso de micro. Modestia aparte.

Por lo demás, se aproxima el concierto de Pascua de la orquesta, que es éste lunes, y todavía estoy decidiendo si voy a participar en él o no. Por desgracia el director ha incluido algunas piezas que son demasiado ambiciosas para algunos de los integrantes. Y yo no quiero ser miembro público del destrozo de la quita de Beethoven o Pompa y Circunstancia de Elgar. Así que dependiendo de cómo sonemos el día del ensayo general, tocaré o no. Además, mi sitio ha sido usurpado ya que no he podido asistir a los ensayos (tenía clase) y ya no me apetece tocar. De todas formas, todavía lo estoy pensando.

Además, voy a tener un invitado durmiendo en mi habitación la próxima semana: nada más y nada menos que el mismísimo Mr. Ian, cuya opusdeística red de contactos y alojamientos ha fallado. Ahora que lo pienso, yo también soy una rama (aunque lejana) de la opusdeística red de contactos y alojamientos... El caso es que va a dormir conmigo (en mi cuarto de 10 metros cuadrados) de lunes a viernes de la siguiente semana. Él viene a la LSE a hacer unas investigaciones para su doctorado, así que imagino que como buen chino estará en la biblioteca de sol a sol. De todas maneras será divertido. Y a lo mejor incluso me pone al día en microeconomía, aunque creo que es demasiado especializado (él es ingeniero, al fin y al cabo).

Me paso la vida dudando del oren de los signos de puntuación. ¿Cuál es la posición? Punto, comillas, nota al pie. Comillas, punto, nota al pie. Nota, punto, comillas. Nota, comillas, punto. ¡¡Y así me paso las horas porque no lo explica nadie en internet!! De todas maneras, ya no me importa. La redacción está entregada, ahora tengo otra para dentro de dos semanas: federalismo. [se frota las manos]. O: [se frota las manos.] Ni idea. La primera queda mejor...

Por cierto, después de que consiguiera terminar los relatos cortos de Kafka (que se me resistieron, he de reconocerlo, qué ser más atormentado) devoré en dos días "Si una noche de invierno un viajero", de Italo Calvino que aprovecho para recomendar desde aquí. Espectacular. ¡Pero ojo! Tiene sepso. O como la llamarían algunos, "con formación". Por favor, por favor ¡compradla y leedla!

Eso es todo por hoy. ¡Llevaba tiempo sin escribir nada! (me está empezando a repatear el signo de exclamación inicial.) o ). ¡¡Ayudadme!! Espero que os vaya a todos bien.

Saludos desde una isla hoy extrañamente soleada.

PS: El cuadro es de Allison Schulnik, una artista norteamericana que me entusiasma últimamente. De recomendaciones musicales, para hoy os dejo Grizzly Bear:


¡¡Quiero leer más!!

viernes, 5 de febrero de 2010

De Stravinsky y la Nueva Derecha

Muy pocas veces pasa, pero de cuando en cuando uno da con un disco en el que cada canción es buena. Cada una de ellas, sin excepción. El último que he encontrado es el debut de una banda de Portland, Oregon que se llaman Fleet Foxes. Un estilo así muy acústico y armónico (vale, no me pasaré con las esdrújulas). Actualmente estoy enganchado a ellos y me encanta. Como siempre, os dejo un vídeo para que lo disfrutéis.


Ya que hablo de música, el lunes pasado fue la segunda vez que tuve la oportunidad de ir a la Royal Opera House (ROH). Lo que vi esta vez no se parecía en nada a las dos operetas (sin que ésto sea un término despectivo, sólo se llaman así) cortas y cómicas y "fáciles de escuchar" de la última vez. Lo de el lunes era una pedazo de ópera de tres horas (tres actos de una hora cada uno) y además de Stravinsky, bien conocido por sus fáciles y poco innovadoras partituras, que harán las delicias de todos los profanos a la música. ¿Quién, al escuchar la consagración de la primavera, no se ha sentido amenazado por algo violento y desconocido? En resumen, ¿a quien no le daban miedo los volcanes de Fantasía? ¿Quién no acababa hasta las narices de tragarse un universo en el que no pasaba nada, esperando que ocurriera algo, y cuando finalmente se llegaba a la tierra, lo único que se movía eran las bolas de fuego voladoras que explotaban?


¡¡Y toda la secuencia, desde que nacía el universo hasta que se extinguían los malditos dinosaurios, duraba media hora!! Reconozcámoslo, todos pasábamos al siguiente capítulo. Y además de hacerse odiar por los niños que vimos Fantasía, generalmente también se hizo odiar por los músicos que tenían que interpretar sus composiciones. La "Danza infernal" del Pájaro de fuego es la obra orquestal más difícil de los últimos tiempos. La cantidad de virtuosismo que todos y cada uno de los miembros de la orquesta tiene que tener para tocar esta pieza es absolutamente ridícula.


Sin embargo, a pesar de que cada uno le ha odiado a su manera, nadie duda en calificar a Stravinsky com uno de los mejores, si no el mejor, músico del siglo XX. Si tuviera que describir lo que he escuchado de su música con una sola palabra sería sobrecogedora. De hecho cuando fui a ver el ballet "el pájaro de fuego" al Real, con unos 8 años (gracias a mi mami que me llevó) me quise morir del miedo. Cuando vi el ballet de "La consegración de la primavera", al real también (y gracias a mi mami, que me llevó) me impresionó tanto como me había impresionado aquel primer ballet. Y si impresiona en los 2000, imaginad en los años 20 cuando fue compuesta.

Así que después de esta digresión, por la que me disculpo, ya os podeis imaginar lo que fue una ópera de Stravinsky. The Rake's progress (en castellano, La carrera del libertino). Sin palabras. Aunque quizá para un novato en ópera como yo se pudo hacer un poco indigesta en algunas partes, la mayoría del tiempo disfruté como en mi vida. Hay un pobre pringao, una novia rica, un padre de la novia rica y un malo malísimo. La historia se seguía muy bien, y la música era una pasada. Además, debe de ser superdifícil de cantar, porque, muy al estilo Stravinsky, los cantantes van por un lado y la orquesta por otro. A pesar de ello, sigue siendo amena y no muy difícil. En resumen, me lo pasé muy bien.

Creo recordar que en alguna entrada anterior dije que el profesor de macroeconomía parecía muy bueno. pues rectificar es de sabios: es espantoso. Es la típica persona muy inteligente 8 de eso no hay duda) pero que fracasa al hacer a los demás partícipes de lo que ocurre en su cabeza. las clases son demenciales. No e entero de nada. Pero nada es nada. llegó la tercera semana y todavía no entendía de qué narices estaba hablando el hombre. Algo como lo que pasaba con ADA. Pero todo cambió cuando decidí comprarme el libro. Ese libro es lo inexplicable, es de oro, es... Ahora lo entiendo todo. El autor, catedrático de macroeconomía de Harvard, lo explica tan bien, tan claro, con sus propios puntos de vista, tan interesante... he pasado del odio al amor hacía la macroeconomía en lo que se tarda en leer la introducción. La micro sigue siendo insulsa, aunque el profesor sea bueno y no es fácil, a mí no es una cosa que me parezca interesante. Así que creo que ya sé hacia qué rama de la economía voy a enfocar mis estudios futuros.

Por lo demás en política nos han devuelto una de las dos redacciones, y como cabía esperar, nos han machacado a todos. Parece que nos quieren dar caña tipo El Moro. yo, que me esperaba una nota bastante decente, no he salido malparado con un 57, pero han rodado cabezas. Y esta vez no he sido el mejor de la clase, porque ha habido dos 62. El próximo martes voy a ir a hablar con el profesor a ver si me puede aconsejar sobre cómo coño quiere que le hagamos las redacciones de las narices. A ver si en la próxima llego al deseado 7. A estos profesores se les aplica la famosa frase, pero cambiando las notas: "el ocho es Dios, yo soy el siete, a ver si conseguís un seis." Y yo pensaba que el Moro era de los más duros. Las narices. El miércoles me dan la de política comparativa, una de las pocas redacciones de política que he escrito de las que estoy orgulloso. Si llego al 7, cosa que dudo, habrá grandes celebraciones.

Un comentario: me encanta cómo se construye el conocimiento académico. Es como una gran escalera, desde la que no se puede subir sin apoyo del anterior, todo basado en el trabajo de los que previamente estudiaron el tema antes que tú, todo construido sobre citas. Me encanta. Por eso voy a subir mi redacción por si puedo inspirar a alguien, y si quiere citarme... es lo bueno que tiene internet: puedo publicarme gratis a mí mismo ,y además llegar a muchísimas personas.


IS THE NEW RIGHT A LIBERAL OR CONSERVATIVE MOVEMENT?

Bosco F. Alava, Queen Mary, University of London

ABSTRACT

The New right is a movement which arose in the sixties, that bases its thinking around the importance of the man as an individual, and thus favours the existence of a free, laisez-faire market and the respect for individual liberties. Neo-liberalism and neo-conservatism have in common that they arose as a response to the damages the free market did in the economy, with individualism as base. In spite of their common points, the irreconciliation if their philosophical roots renders them incompatible. The New right resembles neo-liberalism in its conception of the human being and the economic theory of free market. By contrast, resembles neo- conservatism in the sense that it has a strong “looking back to a golden age” tendency. However, looking back to a primary conservatism in which the welfare state still has not been adopted, or to a neo-conservatism that rejects it, the two ideologies have many common points. However, different factors will lead to the conclusion that New Right belongs to a neo-liberal approach.

This essay will try to give a comparative approach to the “New Right”, and try to classify it as a conservative or liberal movement. Firstly, an introduction to the New Right will be given, followed by a summary of the views of both liberal and conservative groups. An analysis of the neo-conservatism and neo-liberalism, of their similarities and differences and compatibility will follow. Then a detailed analysis of the similarities and differences of the New Right with this schools of thought in both social end economic matters will lead to an answer to the question this essay has for title.

The New Right is a set of ideas that arose in the sixties, and have had influence in the last three decades of political thought. It is said to be “strongly economistic”[1], in the sense that its main lines of consideration are based on the idea of free economic choice rather than the welfare state (as it motivates individuals to depend on benefits), and it favours free market. As with respect to social policy, it is based on (or according to Barry, is a response to)[2] the post-war consensus, and postulates the belief that “the individual human is primary”[3] and thus, the individual should matter over the moral standards. It also believes in voluntary cooperation as more effective than forced and it is hostile to racial, religious and sexual prejudice as well as privilege. Finally, its thought is depicted with the ideas of rationalism and optimism. However, to classify the New right into one of the two most broadly spread political doctrines (liberalism and conservatism), a short analysis of both will be provided.

Liberalism can be shortly defined as “a political orientation that favours social progress by reform and by changing laws rather than by revolution”, and also as “an economic theory advocating free competition and self-regulating market”. [4] Barbara Goodwin defines the main “ingredients of liberalism” as: a conception of the individual being “essentially rational”[5], a government “based on the

Consent of people”[6] with law and a constitution that limit its power, in a society marked by freedom, equality of opportunity and social justice based on merit.

However, this doctrine has evolved to what in this essay will be called “neo-liberalism”, even though this term refers to the classical economic liberalism developed from 1938 by economists and sociologists such as Rüstow. Barbara Goodwin identifies some contemporary principles that are born from liberalism, but “which also challenge it in certain ways”.[7] The most extreme of these is libertarianism, which can be understood as a pure and radical liberalism. Libertarians believe in absolute freedom of thought and speech and the use of state to create greater equality, but at the same time eliminate all the state intervention in economy or other public affairs. Other elements of the new liberalism are nationalism (seen as a reaction against imperialist oppressive regimes) and a renewed “mainstream” liberalism that continues with the traditional approach but with little changes, for example the substitution of the “self-interested individual” for the “self-interested group”. One of the maximum exponents of this set of ideas, Thatcher, is clear about this trend: “There is no such thing as society (…) only individuals and families”[8]

Conservatism, in the other hand is defined as the “political orientation advocating the preservation of the best in society and opposing radical changes”[9]. This political theory is completely opposed to liberalism in the sense that its “view of human nature is an acceptance of the need for (…) authoritarian government”.[10] Again as opposed to liberalism, in economics matter conservatives prefer government intervention on economics affairs.

As well as liberalism, the conservative doctrine has suffered an evolution, which has transformed the actual conservatism in something in many ways different than the ideas that the founders had in mind. The initial conservatism, which favoured the virtues of tradition, and was, over all, mostly an economic doctrine, had been slowly modified to adopt the Welfare state as one of its predominant ideas. Neo-conservatism was a response to this “welfare liberalism”, as Goodwin calls it, that had appeared after World War two. Neoconservative thinkers reject the idea of welfare state and try to return to this “pure” conservatism, by praising the initial liberal individualist approach. Even though conservatism has always been associated with the right in the political spectrum, the term “New Right” does not mean that the movement has to be compulsorily a neoconservative movement.

Even though traditionally, liberalism and conservatism have represented two absolutely different concepts and way of life (tradition vs. reform, free will vs. determinism, welfare state vs. economic liberalism, etc), in their new versions, the thinkers in both sides coincide in much more things than the original founders could have thought. Locke’s primitive individualism seems to be a base for the two, and also both abhor the state intervention. It seems that their origins are similar; both are born as a reaction to the political imbalances after World War two, but most importantly, their purpose is the same. They both arose as a criticism to their origins, driven by “the notion that liberalism and conservatism had failed”[11], and the two of them want to achieve the perfection that their original basis advocated for. At rough draft, it can also be said that both movements have a trend towards equalitarianism and away from authoritarianism.

Nevertheless, the fact that they have so many points in common does not mean that these two movements are the same. The broad differences between them are that the neoconservatives, if not totally preserving traditions, still look back and allow such traditions to influence their new decisions, while the neo-liberals are focused solely on radical change. Also, while the neoconservative movement has a strong preference for law and order, some authors classify some groups inside the neo-liberals as close to anarchism (for example the minarchists).

In spite of their similarities and differences, the fact that both movements exist at the same time means that they have to be either complimentary or contradictory. They both are, as said above, a response to the new generations of free market economic thinking applied since World War Two and the economic instability era that succeeded. In the sense that their aims and objectives are the same, the both movements are complimentary. Nevertheless, when analysed in depth come to light all the differences stated above, that happen because the two movements have very contrastive philosophical genesis. Concepts that seemed communal to both movements in the beginning, such as individualism, are unfolded to the rationalist neo-liberal perspective, contrary to the mistrust of human nature that underlies in the neoconservative theory. Their opposite philosophical roots make this two movements, if not contradictory, at least not complimentary, meaning that it is either one of both that it is going to be present in the new right, and therefore dominate the other, since the New Right is the most eminent doctrine regarding these two movements.

The New Right has many features that can make it belong to a neo-liberal movement. Coming back to the definition portrayed above, and as a movement based fundamentally in economics, it reflects exactly the economic liberal theory: in favour of the choice of individuals on how to spend and earn their money (and deciding on the services they want to pay for). New right thinkers believe in a laissez-faire economy, where excessive interventionism (like in the welfare state) should be avoided. Therefore, free market and competition are the key to an efficient economic system. This reminds to first economic liberalism theories, such as Adam Smith’s, that had been exchanged for more interventionist approaches after the 1929 market crash.

Precisely, the fundaments of libertarianism apply very well to the ideas on which the New Right is based. Both New Right thinkers and libertarians advocate the maximization of individual liberty, and fight the intervention of the state. In fact, their principles are so common that some authors dare to say that “the birth of the New Right occurred when libertarians finally accepted the fact that they had been abandoned by the liberals, used and misled by other radicals and sold out by the conservatives”[12], implying that the New Right owes its origins to, and is based in libertarianism.

The New Right has also many elements in common with conservatism. Its lines of thought have a “pronounced tendency to look back at a supposed Golden age”.[13] This is almost the signature of a conservative, who is opposed to radical change in the belief that all the past was better. Also, New Right thinkers are opposed to the actual conservative economic policies, but as Levitas states,

“Exponents of both strands of the New Right claim, in fact, to be returning to their original nineteenth-century forms, prior to the contamination by the “socialist” ideas of the welfare state”[14]

When taking into account the similarities of New Right with conservatism what comes to mind is the conservatism in vogue today, and then it is obvious that (at least in economic terms, which are the most important when speaking about the New Right) it defends exactly the contrary as nineteenth-century “original” conservatives. Nevertheless, if the term “conservative” has its meaning changed to “early conservative” (i.e., the doctrines that can be seen in Burke’s and Lord Salisbury’s writings), the clash about the conception of the economy (welfare state vs. free economic choice) between actual conservatives and New Right thinkers can be eliminated. However, the social and moral implications of the new right would be “too liberal” for an early conservatism.

Not, however, for neoconservatives who, as stated above, advocate to a “return” to the pure ideals of liberalism, but also having evolved accordingly with the actual times. This evolution makes possible that the neoconservative theory, and neoconservatives themselves are able to cope perfectly with the social and moral implications of the New Right.

Opinions vary between authors at the time of defining the position of the New Right in the political spectrum. While Goodwin directly defines it as a “new ideological variant of conservatism”,[15] Davies states that it is “best defined as neo-liberal, or (…) libertarian”,[16] and so does Barry but Lyons writes that “The New Right reminded many of us that there was life in conservatism after all”.[17] Some, like Green even claim that “the use of the term (New Right) is misleading because the old left-right dichotomy is now defunct”[18].

In spite of that, it seems that the New Right has more elements of liberalism than of conservatism, and more of neo-liberalism than of neo-conservatism. Its strong economistic doctrine of free market and lack of state intervention, as well as the moral approach mattering the individual even over moral standards come from the idea of the natural goodness of human being, a human being that does not need or want an exhaustive or invasive control by the government, neither in markets nor in its personal life. This conception of the human being around which the rest of the thought is built tips the balance considerably in favour of liberalism, and therefore can be concluded that even though not in a complete sense (the tendency to look back to a “golden age” and the importance given to economic policies might remind to an early conservatism), the New Right can be classified as a neo-liberal, if not libertarian, movement.

Bibliography:

Barry, N. (1985) The New Right. London: Croom Helm.

Davies, S. (1985). The Spectre haunting the left. In: Hayek, F.A The New Right enlightenment. Kent: Economic and literary books.

Dionne, E.J. (1991). Why Americans Hate Politics. New York: Simon & Schuster. p. 55

Green, D. (1985). From socialism to the new liberalism. In: Hayek, F.A The New Right enlightenment. London: Economic and literary books.

Goodwin, B (2007). Using political ideas. 5th ed. London: Wiley.

Klatch, R. (1999). A generation divided London: University of California Press

Levitas, R. (1986). The political economy of freedom. In: Levitas, R The ideology of the New Right. Cambridge: Polity Press.

Lyons, P (1996). New left, New right and the legacy of the sixties. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.



[1] Davies, S. (1985). “The Spectre haunting the left”. In: Hayek, F.A The New Right enlightenment. Kent: Economic and literary books. P 23.

[2] See: Barry, N.(1985) The New Right. London: Croom Helm. Preface.

[3] Davies, S. (1985). Op. Cit. P. 21

[4] Cognitive Science Laboratory (Princeton University). Available: http://wordnetweb.princeton.edu/perl/webwn?s=liberalism. Last accessed 24/11/2009.

[5] Goodwin, B (2007). Using political ideas. 5th ed. London: Wiley. P 37.

[6] Goodwin, B (2007). Op. Cit. P 39

[7] Goodwin, B (2007). Op. Cit. P 59

[8] Interview published in “Woman’s own” on 31/10/87. Available in http://www.margaretthatcher.org/speeches/displaydocument.asp?docid=106689. Last accessed 20/1/10.

[9] Cognitive Science Laboratory (Princeton University). Available:

http://wordnetweb.princeton.edu/perl/webwn?s=conservatism. Last accessed 25/11/2009

[10] Goodwin, B (2007). Op. Cit. P 165

[11] Dionne, E.J. (1991). “Why Americans Hate Politics”. New York: Simon & Schuster. p. 55

[12] Lehr, S. & Rosetto Jr. , L.. (10/1/1971). “The New Right credo- libertarianism”. The New York Times magazine. P. 23-24.

[13] Davies, S. (1985). Op. Cit. P. 24

[14] Levitas, R. (1986). “The political economy of freedom”. In: Levitas, R The ideology of the New Right. Cambridge: Polity Press. P 4.

[15] Goodwin, B (2007). Op. Cit. P 171

[16] Davies, S. (1985). Op. Cit. P. 21

[17] Lyons, P (1996). New left, New right and the legacy of the sixties. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. P 71.

[18] Green, D. (1985). “From socialism to the new liberalism”. In: Hayek, F.A The New Right enlightenment. London: Economic and literary books. P 14.

Ahí queda la cosa. Os contaré el miércoles cómo ha ido. Besos o abrazos según corresponda.

¡¡Quiero leer más!!
 

Descodificando a la Reina Mary Copyright © 2009 Bosco F. Alava